HIV AND AIDS
The myths, the virus and the burden of proof
By Kevin Hopkins and Kim Wyness
De Rebus Nov. '00
"Is it possible for one so burdened, to discharge the onus of proving that
HIV does in fact cause AIDS?"
Until President Thabo Mbeki gave attention to reports that drug treatments
were ineffective in forestalling the progress of HIV, we had never heard
that there was any doubt that HIV causes AIDS. Now, after various
conferences and talk-shows, a legal question still resonates unresolved and
possibly waiting to erupt: "Is it possible for one so burdened, to
discharge the onus of proving that HIV does in fact cause AIDS?'
The obvious question: So what if HIV does not cause AIDS?
There are infinite reasons why this question could be important or
significant, depending on who you are. But, despite our identity as
individuals, the answer is relevant to us collectively as the public. The
somewhat ironically labelled 'dissident' group of scientists claims that
there is no true scientific way of establishing that HIV is the cause of
AIDS. If the dissidents are correct, then billions of rands of public money
are being misspent and hundreds of thousands of people have put their lives
in the hands of medical establishment that has erroneously based its
research and treatment on a premise founded on an unsubstantiated
assumption. But if the dissidents are wrong, and the more conventional
'popular' theory that HIV does cause AIDS is correct, then the efforts of
the dissidents to subvert the accepted approaches to treatment are
dangerous and place the public at risk.
The general acceptance of the popular theory - that HIV causes AIDS - has
extremely far-reaching effects. The theory's deep roots have penetrated the
fertile soil of the commercial terrain; there is no better example of this
than in the insurance industry. Insurers are, understandably, reluctant to
accept HIV-related risk. Attempts to exclude HIV-infected insured persons
also exclude AIDS sufferers, usually on the assumption that AIDS is caused
by HIV. The dissident theory, which disputes this, then by obvious
implication becomes significant. The true sugnificance, however, has as yet
not fully materialised.
It's a question of proof
The dissident theory has created ripples in the previously calm pond of
popular thought that there is an accepted causal nexus linking the two
conditions. The dissident view claims that the popular theory of HIV
causing AIDS, although accepted cannot be proved scientifically. This
raises some extremely important questions on the legal issues of evidence
governing the proof of facts. In light of this new dissident theory, a
relevant question is whether the courts are entitled to take judicial
notice of the popular theory, or whether the popular theory - and that
which it represents - is so notorious that it is entitled to be removed
from the evidence.
Is there any good reason to unsettle the general rule that 'he who avers
must prove'? Proof is important because if insurer cannot prove that HIV
causes AIDS then the very basis of many repudiations and exclusions is
without legal justification. When ever we speak of proof, we cannot escape
issues of onus and who carries the burden of proof. This involves a
substantive inquiry into exactly what has to be proved by whom.
Limiting the liability, Exclusion clauses and Exclusionary causes
A contract of insurance must, by definition, clearly identify the risk
against which the insured is covered; for example, the risk of illness,
death or even the cost of medical treatment. To illustrate the point,
consider the risk of falling ill and suppose that the insured does indeed
so ail. It is trite that the onus will rest on the insured to prove that
the risk insured against has materialised, a doctor's report may suffice
for this purpose. In Eagle Star Insurance Co Ltd v Willey 1956 (1) SA 330
(A) Centlivres CI held that the insured must bring his claim 'within the
four corners of the promise made to him'. He promise - in this case the
promise to indemnify - may be limited by a clause excluding a certain
defined risk. The purpose of these 'exclusionary clauses' is to restrict
the insurer's liability. But these restrictions do affect the onus of
proof; if the risk is limited in the contract, then it is the insured who
bears the onus of proving on a balance of probabilities that his claims
falls within the limited description, But Reinecke and Van Der Merwe, in
their work General Principles of Insurance (Durban: Butterworths 1989) at
para 189 contend, we submit correctly, that this does not mean that the
insured must prove that the event on which his claim is based was not
excepted from the risk. The onus of proving that it was so excepted rests
on the insurer.
The point is well illustrated in Aegis Insurance Co Ltd v Consani NO 1996
(4) SA 1 (A) where the policy obliged the insurer to pay the deceased
estate the amount of R1 million should the death result from, inter alia,
an accident or by violent means. The policy went on to provide that the
liability of the insurer was excluded in the case of suicide. The court
confirmed the general rule that the burden of proving that a loss fell
within the excepted peril always fell upon the insurer. In practice this
meant that the insured's deceased estate bore the onus of proving that the
insured was dead and that his death was accidental - no more. There was a
separate onus on the insurer to prove that the cause of death ought to
exclude its liability, in this case because it was caused by suicide. (The
issues in this case complicated matters because in order for the respondent
to show that the death was accidental, he would have to disprove suicide
since that was clearly what the evidence suggested. There was ultimately no
need for the applicant to address the onus that it had to prove suicide
because the initial onus on the respondent to prove that the cause of death
fell within the four corners of the policy had not itself been discharged.)
HIV, AIDS and the burden Of proof
Exclusion from liability in the case of HIV and related risk is done
contractually. Where perils related to HIV have been accepted it will
usually be the insurer who will bear onus of proving that the illness, or
death as it may be, is HIV-related. Practitioners should be cautioned
against simply accepting the applicability of the general rule to every
case because the issue of 'onus' may have been agreed to by the parties
contractually in the policy wording. This type of evidence must be
established by an expert witness. Expert opinion is, in general, required
to explain the workings and reliability of technical matters, The cause of
illness or death by HIV, or indeed the existence thereof is, we submit, a
matter to be determined by an expert, In order to justify the exclusion of
liability, the insurer will have to lead expert evidence which will, on a
balance of probabilities, have to satisfy the court that the illness or
death does in fact follow as a consequence of HIV. If the insurer's expert
witness can do this, then the insurer will have justified his prima facie
case for exclusion.
But, can the insurer repudiate liability on the HIV exception if the claim
is based on the insured being diagnosed with AIDS? Surely, the pure legal
answer to this question will depend on whether the risk of AIDS has also
been excluded from the policy. If the policy wording does not specifically
exclude AIDS, but only HIV-related risks, then the insurer must, in order
to escape liability, be able to prove that AIDS is a consequence of HIV or,
stated differently, that HIV causes AIDS. The dissident argue that this is
an impossible onus to discharge. If they are correct then their
'deconstruction' of the 'HIV causes AIDS' hypothesis could have major
implications for the insurance industry where this consequence is either
presumed or else imported into the assessment of risk.
How uncertain must the cause be not to justify as exclusion of liability?
The dissident view challenges the premise that HIV cause AIDS. The effect
of this challenge means that courts must, in our view, be satisfied that
the insurer has, on a preponderance of probabilities, convinced it that HIV
causes AIDS. The test whether something has been proven on a 'preponderance
of probabilities' involves a comparative analysis between two separate
hypotheses so that the court can, on the evidence available, prefer the one
above the other. The onus will not be satisfied if the party who has the
duty to prove cannot persuade the court that his version is more probable
than the other. In the scenario that we have structured, the insurer would
have to place evidence before the court carrying a reasonable degree of
probability, so that in the words of Lord Denning, a court may say that 'we
think it more possible than notŠ.' (Millar v Minister of Pensions [947] 2AB
ER 372 - 374) Hoffman and Zeffert confirm in their authoritative work The
South African Law of Evidence 4th ed (Durban: Butterworths 1948) at 526
that this formulation has been adopted by our courts.
In this case the rest of the sentence would read to the effect that it
should be established as being more probable that AIDS is caused by HIV
than it is not. This statement is significant because the dissidents claim
that the popular theory is fundamentally flawed to the extent that it
offers no proof that HIV is the cause of AIDS, let alone proof to suggest
that AIDS is more than likely caused by HIV. Whether or not the dissidents
can put forward a better theory as to what causes AIDS is, seemingly,
irrelevant. As Hoffman and Zeffert (above) correctly point out at 526-527,
even if the party who bears the onus is able to produce some evidence in
his favour and the other party none at all, the court may feel that the
evidence produced is insufficiently probable to prove the point. That
raises the obvious question of what exactly the dissidents allege it is
that renders the popular theory fatal.
Questioning the HIV equals AIDS hypothesis - the dissident view
The dissidents argue that it is impossible to prove that HIV causes AIDS
because it has in fact never been proved that a human immunodeficiency
virus exists at all. This is because HIV has been classified as a
retrovirus, and the only scientifically acceptable method of isolating and
identifying retroviruses has never been successfully used in the study of
HIV.
This method apparently involves culturing cells, isolating suspected
retroviral particles and then studying these isolated particles by using
electron micrographs (which are in essence photographs of the virus through
an electron microscope). This is done to ensure that they do indeed possess
the requisite characteristics of a retrovirus. In the initial study in
which HIV was identified, the electron micrograph that was used was
actually of an unpurified cell culture and not of isolated retroviral
particles. Scientists appear to agree that it is impossible to identify
retroviruses in a cell culture - they must, it would seem, first be
isolated.
Subsequent studies in which electron micrographs were taken of isolated
retroviral particles, identified as HIV, serve only to cast doubt over the
accuracy of HIV's classification as a retrovirus, according to the
dissidents. This is because the observed particles do not fit the
description of retroviruses, which are apparently spherical in nature, have
diameters of 100-120nm and are covered in 'knobs' (which are essential for
locking onto the cell membrane of the host cell). The particles identified
as HIV were not spherical in nature, they were considerably larger
(approximately 120-240nm in diameter) and smooth. There are also other
significant differences. It is characteristic for retroviruses to leave the
host cell intact after replication, but the HI virus actually destroyed the
host cell.
Of particular significance to the lawyer and his quest for proof, is the
dissident's claim that, without scientifically isolating and identifying
HIV as a retrovirus, it is impossible to identify an HIV-specific antibody
- the basis of HIV testing. Antibodies are produced by the body's immune
system in response to infectious agents (antigens), and HIV testing
involved testing for the presence of HIV-specific antibodies (antibodies
that are produced only when HIV is present) in the blood. If these
antibodies are present, then it is accepted that the individual has been
exposed to HIV and is therefore infected.
However, the dissidents question the origin of HIV-specific antibodies.
Scientists involved in the initial isolation and identification of HIV used
what they called an 'HIV-specific antibody' to prove the existence of the
HIV. They said that, because these antibodies reacted when exposed to
certain particles, the particles must be HIV. But scientists agree that the
only way to prove that an antibody is specific to one antigen is first to
isolate the antigen and then identify the only antibodies that are present
when that antigen is present. It is, however, apparently impossible to
prepare specific antibodies before the antigen to which they specific has
been isolated. How then, ask the dissidents, could it be possible to have
identified an HIV-specific antibody without first establishing that the
antigen - in this case the retrovirus - exists? The point being made by the
dissidents, it would appear, is that until, the nature of HIV is
scientifically proved, it is impossible to say that it is the cause of
AIDS. There are in fact other interesting and compelling reasons put
forward by the dissidents to suggest that the cause of AIDS may, in itself,
not even be a virus at all. For example, it is well known that viruses
cannot survive outside of a host cell for more than a few hours, yet
haemophiliacs have been known to contract AIDS from blood transfusions
where the plasma is stored for months as a dry, flaky, yellowish powder in
which a virus could apparently not survive. How would it have been possible
for the haemophiliac to get AIDS from a virus if a virus cannot be so
transferred?
These are some of the questions that remain unanswered, even after the
various AIDS conferences and talk-shops. Until they are answered by science
satisfactorily, the legal issue of whether a court ought to be entitled to
assume that HIV causes AIDS is in doubt.
Conclusion
Despite this doubt, insurers can still avoid liability contractually - even
if the cause of AIDS is uncertain - but they may have to revise their
policy wording. If not and if Reinecke and Van der Merwe's approach is
followed by the courts (in the case of the excepted risk in the policy is
HIV-related and if the claim is incidental to the consequences of AIDS),
then the onus of proving that HIV causes AIDS will fall on the shoulders of
the insurer. This is an impossible onus to discharge according to the
dissidents. If the insurer fails, as intimated, then it must be held liable
to indemnify.
Kevin Hopkins Ba LLB (Rhodes) is a lecturer in law at the University of
the Witwatersrand and Kim Wyness Mtech (Chiropratic (TWR) is a chiropractor
in Johannesburg. De Rebus is the magazine of the Law Society of South Africa.